Editorial Volume 4 Issue 2
Department of Community, Rush University Medical Center, USA
Correspondence: Koffitse Atchon, Adjunct Faculty, Rush University Medical Center, Department of Community, Systems and Mental Health Nursing, 600 S Paulina St., #1060A, Chicago, IL, USA, Tel 13129425899
Received: January 26, 2016 | Published: February 2, 2016
Citation: Atchon K. Causal inference in epidemiologic researches: are we making the right decision? MOJ Public Health. 2016;4(2):24–25. DOI: 10.15406/mojph.2016.04.00070
Often scientific researchers from different disciplines concluded the researches studies by stating that they found causality between exposures or cause and disease without making sure all the fundamental criteria were effectively met and verified. Should we continue undermining the quality of our research by not stating appropriately the relationship we found from the studies we conducted diligently and with respect to our scientific credibility?
The causal inference is related to a co variation of the cause and effect. According to the Psychological dictionary defined causal inference as a manner of reasoning which permits an individual to see causal relationships in events and infer associations between and among them.
Most researches studies in the health, social and behavioral sciences may not be concerned about association but with causal relationship in the nature. Solving causal relationship systematically requires certain criteria that emphasize in the rigor of epidemiologic and statistical literature and education.
Sir Austin Bradford Hill also known as Bradford Hill (1897-1991) was an outstanding pioneer in medical statistics and epidemiology,1 who put forwards in 1965 an enormous influence on attempts to separate causal from non-causal explanations of observed associations.2
As general rule, one must make sure the following criteria called The Bradford Hill causality criteria or guidelines3 are stated as follows:
In contrast, the failure to satisfy any or even most of these guidelines does not necessary constitutes evidence that the association is not causal.4
However, we read in many publications that the researchers implied causality without ensuring and confirming that the criteria of Hill-Bradford are met before assuming the causality between the first which proceeded and the second event (exposure or cause and disease). The lack of inadequate decisional findings made Bradford Hill to argue that none of these nine viewpoints can bring indispensable evidence for or against a cause-and-effect hypothesis and none can be required as a sine qua non. What they can do, with greater or less strength, is to help answer the fundamental question – is there any other way of explaining the set of facts before us, is there any other answer equally, or more, likely than cause and effect.5,6 This is a great reminder for researcher to make sure the Hill’s criteria are met when they conclude their decision regarding the causal inferences, and preserve the quality of the researches findings.
The importance of considering the Bradford Hill’s guidelines is crucial while making causal inference and decision in the relationship of consecutive events. The process of translating epidemiologic research findings or scientific evidences into health policies should involve careful considerations of issues such as bias and confounding as well as the ability to interpret the results of researches. Causal inferences may also have substantial economic implications for the community and those who might be held accountable for the exposure.
None.
The author declares no conflict of interest.
©2016 Atchon. This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and build upon your work non-commercially.